Explorations in the studies of cognitive science and the literary history of mind
Thursday, April 19, 2012
Tentative Thesis
Le Brun takes a very deterministic approach to the mapping of human emotions and how they manifest themselves physically. While there is much to his work that remains relevant today, modern psychological trends seem to refute the universality of Le Brun's methods, generally taking a more flexible view of this phenomenon. As such, there is room to propose a compromise between the antiquated and the modern, given that emotion does, inherently, manifest in physical form, however, these manifestations vary dramatically from culture to culture, era to era, and, most importantly, from person to person. In Austen's Persuasion and Haddon's The Curious Incident of the Dog in the Night-Time, particularly, there are clear demonstrations of both correct and incorrect inferences of the physical representations of various emotions. From these instances, the compromise between old and new thoughts becomes more clear.
Thursday, April 12, 2012
The Cost of Attention
In N. Katherine Hayles article Hyper and Deep Attention:
The Generational Divide in Cognitive Modes,
the supposition is leveled that humanity is shifting from one form of attention
to a very different form. The first form, deep attention, which is used most
often in higher education, is “characterized by concentrating on a single
object for long periods (say, a novel by Dickens), ignoring out-side stimuli
while so engaged, preferring a single information stream, and having a high
tolerance for long focus times.” While this form of attention is seen as being
traditional, Hayles notes that, evolutionarily, the more chaotic hyper
attention preceded its patient counterpart. This more capricious form of
attention is “characterized by switching focus rapidly among different tasks,
preferring multiple information streams, seeking a high level of stimulation,
and having a low tolerance for boredom.” There is a sense that the two have to
coexist with in each of us, as we are mere animals in the eyes of biology, yet
we have situated ourselves comfortably atop the food chain, enough so that we
are able to enjoy and reap the benefits of utilizing (the admittedly less
practical) deep attention. Though there are fewer than there once were, there
are still dangers present in the world, and we must be able to draw ourselves
away from Dickens on occasion (no matter how captivating), to ensure that we
may continue to enjoy such a “luxury.”
Hayles’
description of hyper attention seems quite relevant to Frank McCormick’s poem Attention
Deficit Disorder. The first stanza provides
an especially insightful vision of life through the perspective of an
individual who cannot focus in any way other than through hyper attention. The
first line, “I guess I paid attention to the wrong things,” suggests a) that
there is a qualitative value applied to the things on which one chooses to
focus (which may well be true) and b) that the speaker feels his attention is
not at his command, for if it were, he would have likely made an effort to pay
attention to the right things. The following lines depict the minor details to
which the speaker did pay attention, including the “empty space between the
words,” the “silent edges of the textbook,” and also the physical
characteristics of the teacher (i.e., shape, color, wrinkles). Despite being
able to only focus sporadically and on miscellaneous objects, the speaker, in
the final line of the stanza, remarks that he remembers them vividly, even
claiming the capacity to “re-draw them in my sleep.” It could be read and
interpreted to mean he has vivid, almost lucid dreams about the random subjects
of his hyper attention, but either way, waking or dreaming, the stanza as a
whole suggests that, while a Dickens novel may be cumbersome, in small doses,
what hyper attention lands on is locked into the memory with a tenacity that is
formidable.
Autism, Einstein & Facebook
According to PubMed Health, the number of diagnosed cases of
autism is increasing substantially. For instance, “a child who is diagnosed
with high-functioning autism today may have been thought to simply be odd or
strange 30 years ago.” With this in mind, might we consider the possibility
that autism is not a matter of having or not having the condition, but rather
looking at the condition as existing over a continuum, from which none of us is
exempt? That is to say, might we all, to some degree, be affected by the
socially impairing condition known as autism? It would explain the recent boom
in diagnosed cases, especially as we are, as a society, less willing to
consider a child simply “odd or strange,” but instead feel more comfortable
applying a medical explanation for this unusual behavior. An exceptional case
of autism going undiagnosed (although this is widely debated) is that of the
physicist and Nobel laureate Albert Einstein, who purportedly threw tantrums
and preferred solitude. Both of these behaviors are listed in the PubMed Health
article as symptoms of autism.
Furthermore,
it seems plausible that there may be a correlation between increased cases of
autism and the observable decrease in direct, face-to-face, human-to-human (not
to stress the point to much) communication. With the explosion of the
technological industry, the human interactions upon which society once relied
solely have been slowly replaced by more modern electronic means. Granted, the
population that is most affected by this technological usurpation of our most
basic human exchanges is well advanced beyond the age PubMed Health suggest we
are susceptible to developing autism (first 3 years). Rather it may be the
reverse, that is, a broader portion of the population having the condition
would likely encourage the establishment of an alternate form of social
communication. Is this utter speculation? Absolutely. Is there not, though, an
uncanny sense that all of our new contraptions for avoiding human contact have
an especially apparent use to those who have autism?
Wednesday, March 28, 2012
EGAUGNAL or LANGUAGE: Production v. Comprehension
In Stephens and Hasson’s article Speaker-listener neural
coupling underlies successful communication,
the essential distinction between language production and language
comprehension is drawn. From a fundamental linguistic perspective, an
individual is almost always capable of comprehending more language than he or
she can produce. This poses an interesting and curious dichotomy of
neurological language use, as it seems to suggest that the human mind has two
receptacles, if you will, in which language is stored. It seems as though the
first receptacle, where language is initially stored, houses the words and
phrases merely recognized, though not established well enough to duplicate in
usage. The second receptacle, then, houses words and phrases that are familiar
enough to recycle in one’s own language. Theoretically, words that have been
heard in proper use with sufficient repetition will eventually transfer from
the first to the second receptacle, allowing an individual to both comprehend
as well as produce that particular element of language.
This
notion seems to apply, although in a perplexingly reverse manner, to Dean
Young’s poem Handy Guide. Throughout the
piece, Young expresses a series of seemingly bizarre and unrelated thoughts,
all of which containing relatively basic language that ought to be familiar to
most adult users of language. The reversal from the underlying linguistic
notion, that comprehension precedes production, can be observed when considering
the readily accessible nature of most all of Young’s language in the poem
compared to the apparent inane and inexplicable nature of his statements. The
poem begins, for example, with the stupefying couplet, “Avoid adjectives of
scale. / Dandelion broth instead of duck soup.” The poem continues in this
manner and leaves the poor reader with a complete lack of any coherent or
cohesive understanding. It this unusual case, the reader’s ability to duplicate
or produce this language for himself is not at all difficult, but the same
reader’s ability to comprehend anything that he has just read or reproduced is
virtually impossible (besides, of course, applying a series of arbitrary
interpretations to the poem).
This
anomaly of a poem begs the question, is it not possible, then, to say many,
many things that we can almost never truly understand?
Thursday, March 22, 2012
The Grass is Always Greener
Russell Edson’s poem Antimatter offers an innovative representation of a very well
established notion. Humanity has long been familiar with the phenomenon
experienced when an individual has something, but feels as though he/she might
be happier with an alternative thing. This idea has been summed up concisely in
the colloquialism: the grass is always greener. In other words, whenever one believes that
happiness is just out of reach, they might reconsider that which they are
clutching at the present, and perhaps come to the conclusion that what they
have is more than enough to evoke happiness.
The
first and last lines of this poem play an especially crucial role in the
reconfiguration of this ideal. The poem begins, “On the other side of a mirror
there’s an inverse world,” setting up not only the visual concept of a division
between this side and the other, but also using the word inverse to capture the fundamentally backwards nature of
Edson’s hypothetical world. In a
world where such anomalies as insane people going sane and sunrise occurring at
night are the norm, one might consider this arrangement to be completely far
fetched. The surprising and revealing truth of the matter is, however, that in
a world where every person is insane, one is just as concerned about acquiring
sanity as we are of losing it in our world, on our side of the mirror. So,
while the picture Edson paints looks to us like a wild concoction of Tim Burton
and Salvador Dali, it is truly no more bizarre than our world might seem to a
citizen of this inverse society.
Finally,
in the last, and arguably most profound line in Edson poem, we learn, “In such
a world there is much sadness which, of course, is joy . . .” To us, a
reversion from adulthood into childhood, a loss of all the great benefits of
being a cognizant and responsible human, seem very sad indeed. But is it truly
any more sad than the exchange of innocence for corruption, the rise from
peaceful youth to aggressive age. Without Edson’s unique perspective into a
world upside down and backwards in every way, we might be inclined to consider
our own situation to be the very happiest a situation can be. When we consider
it against our own reality, though, it becomes apparent that life is only what
one makes of it. Happiness is achieved only through making the best of one’s
circumstances, not attempting to radically alter them for some invented or
imagined ideal.
Thursday, March 15, 2012
To Feel Or Not To Feel, That Is The Distinction
Suzanne Keen’s article, A Theory of Narrative Empathy, poses an interesting distinction between the
notions of empathy and sympathy. Empathy causes an individual to “feel what we
believe to be the emotions of others,” while sympathy only allows an individual
to experience “feelings for another” (208). In literature, the reader can only
ever hope to get as close to the characters as the author permits. If we are
only given a base description of a character, it is likely that we will become
significantly less emotionally invested in the character’s condition.
Alternatively, is we are given a good deal of insight into the character’s
thoughts and emotions, we stand a much better chance of coming closer to
understanding, appreciating, and ultimately feeling that which the character
feels. This does sound good in theory, which stands to support Keen’s choice of
title, however I am apprehensive to admit that a reader can ever fully
empathize with a fictitious character made of letters and sentences. At best,
we might hope to develop a sense of sympathy for the condition of a given
character.
That
is to say, while I, the reader, could certainly come to a conclusion where “I
feel pity for your pain,” like the physical pain experienced by Louisa from her
fall, or the emotional pain felt by those who witnessed it, I adamantly believe
that one can never truly feel the pain of another, especially not when the
other is comprised solely of symbols (209). It is entirely natural that we, as
insightful and intellectual creatures, can comprehend that the situation of
another is either bad or good or some variation. It seems that the only way one
could truly feel exactly the same physical or emotional sensation as another
would be to experience exactly what the other experienced and through that
individual’s perspective. The former would be difficult enough to orchestrate,
ensuring that each and every detail of the scenario is identical, but the
latter, as far as I am aware, is utterly impossible. Even if the replication of
a single experience were carried out flawlessly, it would be experienced
differently through the filter of the sympathizer’s perception than through
that of the initial subject. For this reason, I doubt whether true empathy can
ever be achieved, especially when the subject of the empathy is a series of
words on a page.
Thursday, February 23, 2012
Skeleton Outline
Title
Geometric Metaphors in the Enlightenment: Squaring the
Circle of the Mind from Cavendish to Joyce
Introduction
Margaret Cavendish’s Poem, The Circle
of the Brain cannot be Squared,
alongside other historical perspectives on and images of cognition, reveals the
crucial role geometric metaphors played in theorizing the brain and mind in the
17th and 18th centuries. Cavendish, like other Enlightenment writers Cudworth,
Dryden and Pope, develops poetic metaphors that specifically called upon the
use of geometric imagery, primarily circle, square and line, to represent
elements of the brain and mind, as well as to explore the function and power of
each. The circle is specifically employed to represent various phenomena within
neuroscience, specifically due to its complex and perpetual nature. Cavendish
utilizes several other geometric shapes, including squares, triangles and
cubes, which are often used to contrast the infinite circle by way of their
rigid linear structure. While one does not typically associate the immensely
complicated inner workings of the brain or mind with mathematics, let alone
geometry, these writers create unique illusions in which the circle becomes
indicative of a higher faculty and a more bounded, restricted shape (often a
square) represents a lesser one. The influence and esteem of this metaphor has
preserved its relevance up to the present, extending its reach from poetry into
the realm of prose, and has even attained for it a planetary or astronomical
dimension in more modern depictions.
Geometry ¶ Topic Sentence
Before looking at some examples of this
geometric imagery in use, it is essential for one to possess a basic
appreciation for the geometric shapes being anthropomorphized in these literary
works.
Cudworth ¶ Topic Sentence
A primary instance of a circle
exemplifying the supreme cognitive function and a baser geometric arrangement
representing a simpler function can be found in Cudworth’s A Treatise Concerning Eternal and
Immutable Morality.
Cavendish ¶ 1 Topic Sentence
Contrary to the poetic imagery set forth by Cudworth, which
suggests the brain is a linear, mechanical device while the mind is a
cyclically perpetual intangibility, Cavendish proposes that “while the Brain is
round, no Square will be,” from which one can immediately infer that the
circular configuration is still more elusive than the square, but it is now
used to represent the brain, rather than the mind.
Cavendish ¶ 2 Topic Sentence
Cavendish also refers to the imagery of a
line, stating, “…each Brain / Hath on a Line been stretched,” yet proposes a
nuanced conception to that of Cudworth, in which the line represents both
simplicity and a futile effort to map the anatomical structure itself.
Dryden ¶ Topic Sentence
In looking at the use of such geometric
allegory among some of Cavendish’s contemporaries, there becomes a slightly
broader implication to the circular image and its accompanying curiosity.
Pope ¶ Topic Sentence
In a similarly distinct fashion, Pope reconstructs the
macabre atmosphere of Oedipus’ blindness in his poem, The First Book of
Statius his Thebais.
Joyce ¶ Topic Sentence
Finally, the geometric metaphor can be
considered from a more modern perspective with the help of Joyce.
Conclusion
From Cavendish to Joyce, the circle has
been an emblematic marker of the incredible majesty and potential of the human
brain and mind. While geometry is rarely thought of as relevant in a discussion
of cognitive faculties, it is clear that scholars from centuries past and up
through the present find it an integral mode of expressing the seemingly
inexpressible. Conveniently, such geometric imagery has certain flexibility,
meaning it can be applied to any number of scenarios, as the brain and mind are
used in myriad settings. The circle stands as the exemplary shape to represent
human cognition, for the simple reason that it has neither a beginning nor an
end, but rather cycles endlessly.
Thursday, February 16, 2012
Unintentionally Adrift: A Breakdown of Chronological Thought
Interestingly, Erasmus Darwin’s
essay on the subtleties of sleep and Jonathan Schooler’s article concerning the
cognitive phenomenon of mind wandering share some uncanny similarities. While
we let our minds wander, we often find ourselves several steps removed from the
original objective or goal that we had set out on. Schooler make note of the
peculiar nature of this phenomenon, explaining how “mind wandering … often
occurs without intention or even awareness that one’s mind has drifted.” The
term ‘executive control’ is used to describe such intentionality on the part of
an individual. An executive decision is how a person’s mind initially arrives
at the specific goal that is being undertaken. In the case of mind wandering,
however, an individual temporarily loses this capacity for the structured
organization of his/her thoughts. This is not, by any means, a rare occurrence
in human cognition (at least not in my case), but this discussion of
intentionality is a curious one, especially given that Darwin entertains an
eerily similar notion in his contemplation of sleep and its accompanying
nuances.
In
Darwin’s essay, the “rapidity of the succession of transactions in our dreams”
is a point upon which particular focus is applied. Whilst asleep, a person is
essentially unable to distinguish between any one point on the timeline of
his/her dream and another, “because this act of comparing requires recollection
or voluntary exertion.” It is here, on the specific topic of purposeful action
versus unconscious meandering, that Schooler’s article becomes intrinsically
akin to the essay offered by Darwin. It seems that, whether asleep or conscious
yet adrift in thought, the mind is lacking an assertive direction which can
cause it to lose any sense of chronology. That chronology can apply either to
the setting and action of a dream sequence or to the sequence of conscious but
aimless thoughts that occur during the phenomenon of mind wandering, or,
perhaps more colloquially, day dreaming.
Darwin
does suggest in his essay that there is some difference to these cognitive
activities. “In our waking hours,” he claims, “we are perpetually making this
comparison, and by that means our waking ideas are kept confident with each
other by intuitive analogy.” That is to say, while awake, we are always
allowing new external stimuli to modify our perception of reality. It might be
fair to say that Darwin’s thoughts on waking perception are true only insomuch
as one’s “intentional pursuit of a goal,” as Schooler puts it, is maintained
steadfastly. Without such intentionality of thought, it seems that, asleep or
awake, one’s thoughts will drift in such a way that the path between thoughts
can scarcely be traced.
Thursday, February 2, 2012
One Book, Three Book, Old Book, E-Book
In his work, Detached Thoughts
on Books and Reading, Charles Lamb
discusses his personal preference for certain books over others, offering
several criteria upon which books can be judged as good, bad, or even unworthy
of being considered a book at all. While he claims, “I can read almost any
thing,” it seems that the value judgment he is placing on some books over
others is based as much on the physical characteristics of a book as on the
content, the actual words. Lamb conjectures that “to be strong-backed and
neat-bound is the desideratum of a volume,” which is to say, a book not only
should, but must be judged by its cover. What appears to be for the very same
reason, he admits, “it moves my spleen to see these things in books' clothing
perched upon shelves, like false saints, usurpers of true shrines, intruders
into the sanctuary, thrusting out the legitimate occupants.” There is, indeed,
some validity to the notion that some crap is simply not literature, despite
how hard it attempts to feign literary worth, or how widely accepted it is by
public audiences. This qualification of written works as literature or
something else is, and has been an ever-present struggle. As far as I can tell
though, such distinctions were almost exclusively drawn according to the
supposed “literary worth” embodied within the pages of a work. Lamb, on the
other hand, seems to be concerned more that “no casket is rich enough, no
casing sufficiently durable, to honour and keep safe such a jewel.” Exactly how
is it that Lamb comes to consider a piece of writing to be a “jewel” worthy of
such ornamental “casing?”
We will not likely have a clear and
certain answer to the question of why written works are sorted into categories
of high art and low art, or no art at all. What is perhaps more interesting
though, as well as being more readily discernable, is what draws people to read
the book they choose. For Lamb, we might conclude that his proclivity for
fancifully adorned books has a direct correlation with those he chose to read.
It should be noted, however, that he also mentions in his disjointed musings on
the matter that “the thousand thumbs, that have turned over their pages with
delight” are perhaps another intriguing element that might very well draw a
reader towards a particular book. There is something to be said for the sheer
history of a book (of a certain age) that gives the reader some sense of
historical context, beyond that offered by the words that lay within. Such
considerations cause Lamb to proffer the inquiries, “Who would have them a whit
less soiled? What better condition could we desire to see them in?” And though
it is something he simply could not have foreseen, there are many today that
might argue that the crispness and ease of use that come with an electronic
edition of a book (on a kindle, nook, or iPad) are, indeed, the “better
condition” of any corresponding version in tangible form. While I happen to appreciate
a book not only for its content, but also for “the sullied leaves, and worn out
appearance, nay, the very odour,” I, too, find the case for such practical
electronic devices to be a compelling one. The lingering question, which only
time can answer for us, is what the “book” will look like in our children’s
lifetimes, and those of our children’s children’s.
Thursday, January 26, 2012
Recalling the Forgotten: Proust & the Mysteries of Memory
While reading of how a simple cup
of tea and a “buttery cookie flavored with lemon zest and shaped like a
seashell” immediately and spontaneously flooded Marcel Proust’s mind with an
overwhelming sense of joy, the thought occurs: What else can seemingly
commonplace occurrences evoke from the depths of our most secluded
subconscious? In his article, Marcel Proust: The Method of Memory, Johan Lerer suggests that Proust had a sort of
uncanny awareness of the value of introspection, or the psychoanalysis of the
self. In mentioning that Proust, unlike his predecessors and contemporaries,
invested a significant deal more into thoughts than he did things (a grave critique of his fellow persons of letters),
it becomes clear that the mind, in Proust’s opinion, was the truly beautiful
and amazing specimen, rather than that which it perceives. Proust’s work
“became a celebration of intuition, of all the truths we can know just by lying
in bed and quietly thinking.” Yet, while a thorough investigation of the
psyche, in a quasi-meditative style, held many secretive riddles to which
Proust sought suitable answers, such bedridden philosophical inquiries would prove
only so fruitful. Lerer makes note of the work of Brown psychologist Rachel
Herz, who, in studying the complexities of Proust’s literature along with the
neurological implications of his revelations, found that, indeed, “our senses
of smell and taste are uniquely sentimental.” It is no coincidence, then, that
Proust should have experienced such an “exquisite pleasure” from such an
apparently ordinary snack.
It becomes even more curious when
this singular instance in Proust’s life is extrapolated to envelope all of our
daily comings and goings. Might we, like Proust, find some deeply hidden,
nearly forgotten memory from the taste of a long-avoided food, or from the
distinct odor of some place where we have not been in ages? And for that
matter, is it not possible that such a revival of sensation and thought might
bring us the exact antithesis of “exquisite pleasure,” or any emotional shade
of grey falling in between? This presents a rather strange possibility. When
one least expects it, he may be immersed in any conceivable emotional state,
and without so much as a sign of warning. Proust finds nearly perfect words for
the dumbfounding inquiry that strikes at the heart of this phenomenon: “Will it
ultimately reach the clear surface of my consciousness, this memory, this old,
dead moment which the magnetism of an identical moment has traveled so far to
importune, to disturb, to raise up out of the very depths of my being?” Just as
Proust, himself, cannot provide a definitive response to such a confounding
dilemma, is it more likely than not that we, too, will be unable to reach the
solace that he does in The Episode of the Madeleine. At least, for his sake, he finally comes to the
realization that the root of his joy is derived from the long-lost memories of
a cherished aunt. The most haunting element of this discussion seems to be the
problem of discerning this origin. Just imagine the mounting frustration of
finding such an impetus as Proust’s Madeleine, experiencing its visceral
effects, and being yet unable to arrive at the source of your state of
heightened emotional response. Such baffling feelings, without any reasonable
explanation, might be comparably horrifying to being drugged with a
hallucinogen without your express knowledge. Such maddening futile curiosity
might well be simply unbearable.
Saturday, January 21, 2012
Paying Attention to Attention: The Instructor-Instructee Cognitive Quandary
Attention may well be one of the
single most complex elements of human cognition. Like the young pupils
described by Maria Edgeworth in her comprehensive study of attention in an
educational environment, how, exactly, can any person selectively apply their
attention to the plethora of stimuli present throughout our world, and
successfully manage to not become desperately overwhelmed by the prospect of
retaining or benefiting from any single observation? This perplexing inquiry
relates poignantly to the timeless philosophical query of “whether attention
was directed voluntarily or involuntarily towards objects and events” (P &
J, 4). Through several anecdotes offered on the matter, each one framing the
discussion in a slightly different setting, Edgeworth seems to suggest that
these are not mutually exclusive options for the mysterious function of
attention as it pertains to the larger issue of human cognition. On the one
hand, passively strolling through space and time, seemingly oblivious to one’s
surroundings, and only occasionally noting peculiar or exceptional instances,
and largely by chance, at that, a person could be said to be engaged in
involuntarily attention. On the other, a person might be said to be
participating in a voluntary use of attention, conscientiously taking in every
detail (or as many as possible given the circumstances) with a concerted effort
directed towards the accumulation of useful and advantageous discoveries of the
world within which we exist. While this may have seemed to philosophers, at
some point in human history, as a logical and, furthermore, necessary
distinction, it seems to be Edgeworth’s stance on the matter that this
divergence in behavior and cognitive activity are more accurately described as
stages of one’s educational development, as opposed merely to representing
one’s cognitive type or individualism.
In discussing the most appropriate
manner with which to educate a student on new material, Edgeworth mentions the
important distinction between the perspective of an educator and that of a
pupil. One must not forget that a child learning something for the first time
is seeing the topic of focus in a fundamentally different way from the
instructor who likely knows the contents of the lesson like the back of her
hand. As Edgeworth informs us, “we often expect, that those whom we are
teaching should know some things intuitively, because these may have been so
long known to us that we forget how we learned them” (E, 3). That is not to say
that, through time and exposure, our reliance on attention is at all
diminished. Nor is it fair to conclude that the student requires the use of any
more or less attention than the teacher to accomplish the same task. Rather,
the student is simply in a different, and much earlier, stage of applying
attention to the task at hand, and, in turn, is also at an infant stage of
interpreting the data collected by the attention that has been invested in said
task. A teacher may have forgotten how she has come to know so well something so
complicated, and she may, as a result, view a student’s difficulty to
grasp the subject matter as a failure to apply the requisite attention, but it
is, in actuality, the same amount of attention being applied by both parties
(assuming a standard of commitment and initiative on behalf of both, but
especially on the pupil). It seems to be different, and drastically so at that,
due to the simple explanation that repetition, rather than diminishing the
necessary attention invested into a given task, simply deceives the
practitioner into feeling as though less attention is required. In reality, the
same level of attention is applied to the task for both teacher and student,
although it has, through innumerable reiteration, become second nature to the
educator, while it remains a mystifying puzzle to the pupil, due to an utter lack
of contact with the material in question.
Thursday, January 12, 2012
The Futility of Life and Death
In language similarly inaccessible
to that used by Keats in his poem When I Have Fears, yet discussing a matter equivalently relatable, as
it pertains to the human condition and basic human nature, Margaret Cavendish’s
poem, The Circle of the Brain Cannot be Squared, discusses the inherent desire to uncover that,
which is fundamentally unknowable. In her own words, she describes the futility
of an investigation “for that, which is hardest to find.” For Keats, the topic
of discussion is the inevitable demise we all face, a mystery that rests at the
end of each of our lives. Yet, for Cavendish, the quagmire being discussed
involves the unfathomable inner-workings of the human mind. Cavendish uses
several mathematic, and specifically geometric references to characterize the
complex notions surrounding the mind and the root of its unattainable
functions. It seems as though the “Circle of the Brain,” being the primary
representation of how the mind works, is cleverly apt, given the infinite
possibilities available to its beholder. In his article, Brain and
Mind in the Long Eighteenth Century, C.U.M.
Smith elaborates on the many different theories proposed by such noble minds as
Plato, Descartes, Newton, and many others, each offering variations as to the
medical explanation of the seamless interactions of the mind, soul and body. In
what would appear a similarly scientific and geometric characterization of each
proposed rationalization, Cavendish uses the imagery of triangles and squares,
along with division and subtraction to indicate the implausibility of managing
to “Square a Circle round,” or to explain that which is simply unexplainable.
So, just as Keats concludes his sonnet with an admission that he cannot escape
the scythe of death, it looks as though Cavendish has similarly succumbed to
the realization that the mind cannot, and never will, be fully grasped by any
of the hard sciences. While we can continue to divide and subtract, to break
down elements that we believe to be true in search of answers to the ultimate
questions, there is little hope of transforming our limited knowledge of a
boundless, circular phenomenon, like the mind, into a rigid, calculated
machine-like instrument.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)